Why does marx hate capitalism




















However, he also claimed that capitalism is path-dependent — where it goes next depends on where it last came from. While it is not necessarily a problem that exponential technological and productive gains would be immune from undoing, Marx also argued that monopolisation from the centralisation and concentration of capital grows congruently with such phenomena, and is problematically also immune from long-term reversals.

Marx viewed production as a circuit accumulating capital for the producers. In order to best accomplish this, the natural tendency over time for a firm is to increase constant inputs and reduce variable inputs labour. If the Labour Theory of Value holds, the gradual reduction in variable inputs means the real value of goods produced declines over time. Profits slowly decrease and the capital accumulation circuit gradually loses momentum.

At some point, the forecast for the next circuit is a loss. The circuit is not undertaken, and the economy stalls. Marxism rejects static models that produce a simultaneous outcome. Marx proposed that the vast time constraint disproportionality between supply and demand is a critical factor in the instability of capitalism.

Specifically, he argued that supply side decisions are based on probabilistic assumptions about future demand. This then leads to revolutions and the socialization of the productive forces. But above all it comes from the comprehensive view of the economic process: while the models of the scientific mainstream essentially reduce the economy to the market process, the Marxian presentation links together the profit mechanism, the development of technology, working conditions, social conflicts and the cultural consequences of the commodity economy into a vast, cogent narrative of capitalist dynamics, down to its possible end.

In the eyes of capital, things and human beings appear in the world only insofar as they are profitable: we still experience this years after the first edition of Kapital in various ways that are highly relevant. Why, then, read Kapital once again, when its prognoses have become so realistic in our time?

When the concentration of big industries, the privatization of communication networks, the industrialization of agriculture immediately suggest the need for their political control; when the public assets of the earth must be protected against their capitalist privatization; when the destruction of nature cries for global control — and when such demands are no longer a political taboo?

Das Kapital lays bare the covert violence initiated by capitalism and the real sources of wealth: actual labour, the cooperation in a society of knowledge and skills grown up over generations. It is anything but fatalistic or mechanistic. In the end, we are confronted by the insight that the constraints to which we are subject are man-made, and can therefore be changed by human beings.

And they must be changed if the earth is not to become a desert and humankind an appendage of the profit machine; if societies are not to live under than their possibilities. RE: Das Kapital. In this sense they seek to abolish capital. They believe that private ownership of the means of production enriches capitalists owners of capital at the expense of workers. In brief, they argue that the owners of the means of production exploit the workforce. Private ownership over the means of production and distribution is seen as creating a dependence of non-owning classes on the ruling class, and ultimately as a source of restriction of human freedom.

His relentless criticism of capitalism and his corresponding promise of an inevitable, harmonious socialist future inspired a revolution of global proportions.

It seemed that—with the Bolshevik revolution in Russia and the spread of communism throughout Eastern Europe—the Marxist dream had firmly taken root during the first half of the twentieth century. That dream collapsed before the century had ended.

The people of Poland, Hungary, Czechoslovakia, East Germany, Romania, Yugoslavia, Bulgaria, Albania, and the USSR rejected Marxist ideology and entered a remarkable transition toward private property rights and the market-exchange system, one that is still occurring.

Which aspects of Marxism created such a powerful revolutionary force? And what explains its eventual demise? The answers lie in some general characteristics of Marxism—its economics, social theory, and overall vision. If a pair of shoes usually takes twice as long to produce as a pair of pants, for example, then shoes are twice as valuable as pants.

In the long run, the competitive price of shoes will be twice the price of pants, regardless of the value of the physical inputs. Although the labor theory of value is demonstrably false, it prevailed among classical economists through the midnineteenth century.

Adam Smith , for instance, flirted with a labor theory of value in his classic defense of capitalism, The Wealth of Nations , and David Ricardo later systematized it in his Principles of Political Economy , a text studied by generations of free-market economists.

So the labor theory of value was not unique to Marxism. Marx did attempt, however, to turn the theory against the champions of capitalism, pushing the theory in a direction that most classical economists hesitated to follow. Marx argued that the theory could explain the value of all commodities, including the commodity that workers sell to capitalists for a wage. Marx, using principles of classical economics, explained that the value of labor power must depend on the number of labor hours it takes society, on average, to feed, clothe, and shelter a worker so that he or she has the capacity to work.

In other words, the long-run wage workers receive will depend on the number of labor hours it takes to produce a person who is fit for work. Suppose five hours of labor are needed to feed, clothe, and protect a worker each day so that the worker is fit for work the following morning. If one labor hour equaled one dollar, the correct wage would be five dollars per day. Marx then asked an apparently devastating question: if all goods and services in a capitalist society tend to be sold at prices and wages that reflect their true value measured by labor hours , how can it be that capitalists enjoy profits —even if only in the short run?

How do capitalists manage to squeeze out a residual between total revenue and total costs? Capitalists, Marx answered, must enjoy a privileged and powerful position as owners of the means of production and are therefore able to ruthlessly exploit workers.

Marx was correct when he claimed that classical economists failed to adequately explain capitalist profits. But Marx failed as well. By the late nineteenth century, the economics profession rejected the labor theory of value.



0コメント

  • 1000 / 1000